EssaysForStudent.com - Free Essays, Term Papers & Book Notes
Search

View on God

By:   •  Research Paper  •  10,356 Words  •  January 26, 2010  •  887 Views

Page 1 of 42

Join now to read essay View on God

There are only three possible ways of proving the existence of God by means of speculative reason. All the paths leading to -this goal begin either from determinate experience... or they start from experience which is purely indeterminate ... or finally they abstract from all experience, and argue completely a priori, from mere concepts, to the existence of a supreme cause. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A59O/B618

Kant tells us that there are exactly three ways of proving the existence of God by speculative reason. In the first, we begin from "determinate experience and the specific constitution of the world" and ascend from there to a supreme cause. "The world presents to us so immeasurable a stage of variety, order, purposiveness, and beauty" (A622/B650) that we may infer a sublime and wise cause (A625/B654). This is the physico-theological proof or argument from design. In the second, we begin from indeterminate experience or "experience of existence in general" and proceed once again to a cause. Here it does not matter what the world is like, but only that it exists; if the cosmos consisted of nothing but a speck of dust, we would still need to posit a cause for it. This is the cosmological proof. Finally, we may bypass experience altogether and argue "completely a priori, from mere concepts." This is the ontological proof, most audacious of all, as it premises nothing about what exists. In this chapter I examine what Kant has to say about the cosmological and ontological proofs. I consider them (as Kant does) as attempts to prove the existence not of the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, but of a primordial being, whose identity with the God of religion must be a matter of further argument or faith.

A. The Ontological Argument

The version of the ontological argument Kant considers is that of Descartes, not Anselm. 1 It may be set forth as follows:

1. The ens realissimum (i.e., God) is, by definition, the being who possesses all perfections.

. Since (a) existence is a perfection, (b) any being that possesses all perfections must exist. 3. Therefore, the ens realissimum exists.

Kant is generally credited with originating what has become the standard criticism of the ontological argument--that existence is not a predicate. His critique contains in addition two other objections that he and his commentators do not always keep separate from the first: in a predicative proposition you may always "reject the subject," and there is something logically defective in the concept of a necessary being. I argue that one of these criticisms is cogent while the other two--including the famous one--are not.

B. Real Predicates

Kant never enunciates the slogan so often attributed to him, that existence is not a predicate. What he says instead is that existence is not a real or determining predicate, that is, "a predicate which is added to the concept of the subject and enlarges it" (A598/B626). As always, by a 'predicate' he does not mean a linguistic item but a property or a constituent of a concept. His contention may be understood in accordance with the following definitions:

A predicate P enlarges a concept C =Df ◇ ∃x(Cx & -Px). (Note that "enlarge" may be a misleading term, insofar as enlarging a predicate typi cally results in narrowing its extension.)

A predicate P is a real predicate =Df P enlarges at least one concept. 2

It follows from these definitions that a predicate P is nonreal iff for any concept C, □(x)(Cx & Px iff Cx). This makes clear the sense in which a nonreal predicate "makes no addition" to any concept: if P is nonreal, then saying that something is both C and P says nothing not already implied by simply saying that it is C. 3

Is Kant correct in claiming that existence is not, in the sense just defined, a real predicate? Yes, indeed: there is no concept C such that ∃x(Cx & -Ex). This, at any rate, is a consequence of letting the existential quantifier express existence. 4 To suppose there is something (∃x ...) that does not exist (... -Ex) is to suppose there is something that there is not.

Relative to widely accepted assumptions, then, Kant's dictum is true. The next question is, how does it show that Descartes's argument is wrong? How does the fact that existence is not a real predicate invalidate the ontological argument or make it unsound?

One common suggestion is that only real predicates may be used in definitions, in which case it would be illegitimate for Descartes to define God as a being who, among other things, exists. 5 But this suggestion

Download as (for upgraded members)  txt (63 Kb)   pdf (592.3 Kb)   docx (34.5 Kb)  
Continue for 41 more pages »