Does Synesthesia Undermine Representationalism?
By: Anna • Research Paper • 3,996 Words • November 20, 2009 • 993 Views
Essay title: Does Synesthesia Undermine Representationalism?
Does synesthesia undermine representationalism?1
Torin Alter talter@ua.edu
[Draft: please treat as such. For Pysche symposium on Gregg Rosenberg’s A Place for
Consciousness: Probing the Deep Structure of the Natural World (OUP, 2004)]
Does synesthesia undermine representationalism? Gregg Rosenberg (2004) argues that it
does. On his view, synesthesia illustrates how phenomenal properties can vary
independently of representational properties. So, for example, he argues that sound/color
synesthetic experiences show that visual experiences do not always represent spatial
properties. I will argue that the representationalist can plausibly answer Rosenberg’s
objections. On reflection, synesthesia poses no serious threat to representationalism.
Rosenberg’s argument from synesthesia resembles anti-representationalist arguments
advanced by Ned Block (1995, 1996), Christopher Peacocke (1983) and others (e.g.,
Boghossian and Velleman 1989). Like Rosenberg, these philosophers argue that
representationalism delivers implausible analyses of certain sorts of (actual) experiences.
Michael Tye (2000) provides plausible representationalist replies to those objections. In
particular, Tye shows how the objections often depend on oversimplified
characterizations of the relevant representational properties. Some of my arguments will
involve applying Tye’s reasoning to Rosenberg’s argument.
Rosenberg’s discussion of synesthesia and representationalism is a small part of his
defense of panexperientialism, “the view that experience exists throughout nature and
that mentality (i.e., a thing requiring cognition, functionally construed) is not essential to
it” (p. 91).2 His concern is that on panexperientialism there might be “protoconscious”
experiences that do not represent anything because they are not associated with any
cognitive system. However, I will argue, it is not so clear that, given panexperientialism,
association with a cognitive system is required for representation. Thus, I will argue that
the panexperientialist has no compelling reason to resist representationalism. But I will
put off discussion of panexperientialism until the end. I will concentrate mostly on
Rosenberg’s argument that synesthesia undermines representationalism, which does not
depend on panexperientialist assumptions and has independent interest.
Representationalism
Representationalism concerns the relationship between phenomenal and representational
properties. Phenomenal properties are, roughly, properties that constitute what it’s like to
have an experience, such as seeing red or feeling pain.3 Representational properties are
properties that represent things as being a certain way. For example, such a property
might represent that there is a red object in the vicinity. Representational properties can
be more or less accurate (Siewert 1998), depending on whether and to what extent the
world is as represented. In John Searle’s (1983) terminology, they have (or are)
conditions of satisfaction.
Representationalism is the view that phenomenal properties are representational
properties. On this view, for every phenomenal property P (in a given class of
phenomenal properties) there is some representational property R such that necessarily an
experience has P if and only if it has R (cf. Chalmers 2004, section 3). Many find
representationalism